0 ^ 0 is one, because the product of zero numbers must leave any previous element undisturbed. Therefore 0^0 = 1.
Rob wrote:By assuming that there is only one infinity and it is neither negative nor positive, then there is no problem with saying n/0 = infinity.
wendy wrote:0 ^ 0 is one, because the product of zero numbers must leave any previous element undisturbed. Therefore 0^0 = 1. The proof does not require division of zero, no more than a count of zero elephants requires the insertion and removal of an elephant.
PWrong wrote:When we say 1/0 is infinity, which infinity are we generally talking about? Can it be shown that it's the cardinality of the integers, or the reals, or both?
batmanmg wrote:(0/0) / (0/0) all real numbers divided by all reall numbers?
wendy wrote:bo seems to suggest, that because 0^m = 0 for all positieve m, that it must be true for all values of N.
bo198214 wrote:(1/n)^(1/n) -> 1
(1/n^n)^(1/n) -> 0
bo198214 wrote:0 * (1/0) = 0 (identity of +) but of course 0/0=x/x=1 too.
Since we can derive 0 in N (which can be done without decrement),
...
On the other hand, division by zero, requires a decrement.
It is this decrement that causes the problem.
wendy wrote:1/0 is generally taken to be the horotopic infinity U. This is the same as the circumference of a horocycle in both euclidean (straight line) and hyperbolic geometries.
wendy wrote:0/0 is generally undefined, not because of division by zero is undefined, but because the equal sign breaks down.
I even chose them completely positive, because you mentioned that the flaw would be them crossing positive/negative. But till now no response from you. In the contrary you even insist that 0^0=1 on the real numbers instead of restricting it to natural, interger or rational numbers. Though by your argument that the 0 of Z is also the 0 of R (which I however dont support) it would follow that 0^0 is undefined throughout.
The other counter argument I still got no response from you is about your most stated (in various disguises though) zero as a counting number.bo198214 wrote:0 * (1/0) = 0 (identity of +) but of course 0/0=x/x=1 too.
Maybe though thats a bit cryptic, so I will explain. If 0 is a counting number then must 0*a = 0 no matter what a. If I now let a=1/0 then would 0=0*(1/0)=0*1/0=0/0. But you at least admit that 0/0 is undefined. This shows that we must be cautious about a. And in the same way we must be cautious about the a in a^0. Because multiplicatively 0 and 1/0 (or 1/infty and infty) are opposite infinities.
Though I think its already a heavy burden of proof, I am still interested what you mean by your sometimes mentioned stability (I intuitively would think that the above two sequences show an instability at 0). And what you meant by this:Since we can derive 0 in N (which can be done without decrement),
...
On the other hand, division by zero, requires a decrement.
It is this decrement that causes the problem.
bo198214 wrote:We can define ^ on RxN by induction (as above taking the multiplication on RxR). And have again that 0^0 can only be defined as 0 or 1 if the operation on the other values of RxN should be left unchanged.
We can define ^ on RxN by Cauchy sequences (taking ^ defined on QxN). Then 0^0 can be defined as 1 and 1 is the only value that it can take.
wendy wrote:0^0 is the same thing throughout.
The limit of 0^x as x-> 0 differs as x starts negative or positive, and is inconclusive.
wendy wrote:The argument that 0^0 = 1, is based on the set N, and therefore must carry through to R.
One can of course, suggest alternate limits from using different directions, but in every case, 1 is a valid substitute.
The further point that if 0^0 is not 1, then it makes all mathematics unstable, since, eg 7 is a product of one 7 and zero 0, and therefore can be written as 7^1 * 0^0. Since 0^0 has an indefinite value, then so does 7.
The argument about the various infinities, makes the fatal mistake that "infinity" is a place. The reality is that "infinity" is a sense of /far away/. That is, one can never really be "far away", but that "here" and "there" shift.
The proposition of 0 = 1/U is not a mathematically precise statement, but a statement of our abilities to resolve 1/U from 1/(U+1) or something like this.
The further point that if 0^0 is not 1, then it makes all mathematics unstable, since, eg 7 is a product of one 7 and zero 0, and therefore can be written as 7^1 * 0^0. Since 0^0 has an indefinite value, then so does 7.
wendy wrote:Thirdly, one can not draw any valid conclusion simply by looking at the approaches to x^r, for r < 0, because the sign of x^r depends on parity of r, which is undefined for real numbers. One can only use magnitude, which approaches 1, for fuzzy values of x and r.
bo198214 wrote:(1/n)^(1/n) -> 1
(1/n^n)^(1/n) -> 0
wendy wrote:If you write the equation as eg exp( k.ln(u)/(u)), then this suggests that the value goes to one as u goes large and k is constant.
If you write something in the form of 1/(n^n)/(1/n),
this is pretty much something of the form of 1/(n)^(n/n) = 1/n.
This particular line, suggests that the asymtope is someting in the order of the number of digits in the base (1+1/n), for which the logrithm is already 1/n. The asymtope is scaresly divisible from that of approaching along the line of 0^n = n.
wendy wrote:This holds true, not only for a in the integers, because we can apply meaning of fraction, in that a^(1/n) = x, implies P(x,x....,x) = x ×@ n = a. Since the process remains valid as we extend the naturals to the reals, the argument that 0^0 = 1 is therefore true.
but there is one that changes sign in the process (going to positive to unsigned).
All the approach from zero tells us is that as one approaches x^y as y approaches 0, is that the expression becomes closer to 1.
It is possible to extend any integer sequence to cover the real number line, by extracting roots (square roots, cube roots), that ever approximate the real values. In any of these cases, the argument of P() = 1 holds true, and therefore this must be the case in the reals also (unless we are to believe that the set Z is not a subset of R).
The argument that 0^0 = 1, does not make any statement regarding division by zero.
...
However, the argument that 0^0 = 1 does not resolve on division
One of the arguments presented (the limit of (1/n)^n),
otherwise is so incorrect that even Cantor distinguishes between infinity (aleph_0), and 2^infinity (aleph_1).
Users browsing this forum: No registered users and 1 guest